106 points by thadt 8 hours ago | 33 comments
thadt 8 hours ago
This reminds of of that one time when I was on a date with a girl from the history department who somehow bemusedly sat through my entire mini-lecture on comparing infinite sets. Twenty years and three kids later, she'll still occasionally look me straight in the eye and declare "my infinity is bigger than your infinity."
charlieyu1 41 minutes ago
I taught my wife simplex algorithm for linear programming and she forgot all of it

Turns out I’m neither good in maths nor teaching

gnulinux 2 hours ago
Wow, I did a very similar thing on the first date with my now wife. I explained the halting problem, and Godel's incompleteness theorems. We also talked about her (biomedical) research, so it wasn't a one sided conversation.

I think dominating on a first date is a risk (which I was mindful of) but just being yourself, and talking about something you're truly passionate about is the key.

dcchuck 8 hours ago
This is the type of romcom I'd watch ;)
wvlia5 7 hours ago
Once I taught the binomial coefficient formula to a girl after sex
grues-dinner 6 hours ago
"So you see if the chance of pregnancy is constant per..uh..encounter, and given that the condom just broke, we're on a spectrum from the chance of a second round roughly doubling the odds but the overall chance is still small, or it doesn't make much difference anyway. Either way, the numbers say we should go again."
dominicrose 6 hours ago
that's not too abstract, I can see how this formula applies to sex

I tried using if for this: https://adventofcode.com/2023/day/12 but computer said no

mbork_pl 7 hours ago
The Fibonacci sequence might have been more appropriate.
lo_zamoyski 6 hours ago
Not if they were using contraception.
huflungdung 7 hours ago
[dead]
grues-dinner 7 hours ago
Fittingly this is roughly the same vintage as your relationship then: https://youtu.be/BipvGD-LCjU
2 hours ago
pfdietz 33 minutes ago
Way back then, calculus was a culture war battleground. Bishop Berkeley famously argued the foundations of calculus weren't any better that those of theology. This sort of thing motivated much work into shoring them up, getting rid of infinitesimals and the like (or, later, making infinitesimals rigorous in nonstandard analysis).

https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/The_Analyst

7 hours ago
muragekibicho 8 hours ago
[flagged]
KeplerBoy 8 hours ago
You would not. People love hearing about the things you care about as long as you can present them in interesting ways. Try it!
halfmatthalfcat 8 hours ago
There’s something called “not giving a fuck” that works in those situations. The crux of it though is you need to “know thyself” or you’ll be forever your worst critic and enemy.
HPsquared 8 hours ago
Also you're being open and readable to the other person. You're not being deceptive or putting on a show, which is usually what rustles people's jimmies.
8 hours ago
Cthulhu_ 8 hours ago
I wouldn't go on Hinge if that's the default experience.
fknorangesite 5 hours ago
It is not, of course.
MontyCarloHall 7 hours ago
Get this incel trolling out of here. No, all that would happen if your date weren’t interested in math/whatever you’re into is a polite message “I had a great time but I don’t think we have much in common” and leave it at that.
DonHopkins 7 hours ago
His oddly specific fear of being "plastered on a bunch of facebook new-york-dating-experience groups" sounds like women have had to warn each other about him before, and it probably wasn't about his interest in math, but something much worse.
btilly 5 hours ago
I'm curious. Did either of you ever notice the implicit philosophical assumptions that you have to make to come to the conclusion that one infinity can be larger than another?

Despite the fact that this was actively debated for decades, modern math courses seldom acknowledge the fact that they are making unprovable intellectual leaps along the way.

mensetmanusman 1 minute ago
Don’t worry, we have only decided that there are two sizes of Infinitis- normal ones and really big ones.
dragonwriter 5 hours ago
> Despite the fact that this was actively debated for decades, modern math courses seldom acknowledge the fact that they are making unprovable intellectual leaps along the way.

That’s not at all true at the level where you are dealing with different infinities, usually, which tends to come after the (usually, fairly early) part dealing with proofs and the fact that all mathematics is dealing with “unprovable intellectual leaps” which are encoded into axioms, and everything in math which is provable is only provable based on a particular chosen set of axioms.

It may be true that math beyond that basic level doesn’t make a point of going back and explicitly reviewing that point, but it is just kind of implicit in everything later.

btilly 5 hours ago
I guarantee that a naive presentation doesn't actually include the axioms, and doesn't address the philosophical questions dividing formalism from constructivism.

Uncountable need not mean more. It can mean that there are things that you can't figure out whether to count, because they are undecidable.

godelski 2 hours ago

  > I guarantee that a naive presentation doesn't actually include the axioms
But you said "modern math courses". Are you now talking about a casual conversation? I mean the OP's story is that his wife just liked listening to him talk about his passions.

  > Uncountable need not mean more.
Sure. But that doesn't mean that there aren't differing categories. However you slice it, we can operate on these things in different ways. Real or not the logic isn't consistent between these things but they do fall out into differing categories.

If you're trying to find mistakes in the logic does it not make sense to push it at its bounds? Look at the Banach-Tarski Paradox. Sure, normal people hear about it and go "oh wow, cool." But when it was presented in my math course it was used as a discussion of why we might want to question the Axiom of Choice, but that removing it creates new concerns. Really the "paradox" was explored to push the bounds of the axiom of choice in the first place. They asked "can this axiom be abused?" And the answer is yes. Now the question is "does this matter, since infinity is non-physical? Or does it despite infinity being non-physics?"

You seem to think mathematicians, physicists, and scientists in general believe infinities are physical. As one of those people, I'm not sure why you think that. We don't. I mean math is a language. A language used because it is pedantic and precise. Much the same way we use programming languages. I'm not so sure why you're upset that people are trying to push the bounds of the language and find out what works and doesn't work. Or are you upset that non-professionals misunderstand the nuances of a field? Well... that's a whole other conversation, isn't it...

btilly 1 hour ago
Your guesses at what I seem to think are completely off base and insulting.

When I say "modern math courses", I mean like the standard courses that most future mathematicians take on their way to various degrees. For all that we mumble ZFC, it is darned easy to get a PhD in mathematics without actually learning the axioms of ZFC. And without learning anything about the historical debates in the foundations of mathematics.

zozbot234 2 hours ago
The "philosophical questions" dividing formalism from constructivism are greatly overstated. The point of having those degrees of undecidability or uncountability is precisely to be able to say things like "even if you happen to be operating under strong additional assumptions that let you decide/count X, that still doesn't let you decide/count Y in general." That's what formalism is: a handy way of making statements about what you can't do constructively in the general case.

To be fair, constructivists tend to prefer talk about different "universes" as opposed to different "sizes" of sets, but that's all it is: little more than a mere difference in terminology! You can show equiconsistency statements across these different points of view.

btilly 1 hour ago
Yes, you can show such equiconsistency statements. As Gödel proved, for any set of classical axioms, there is a corresponding set of intuitionistic axioms. And if the classical axioms are inconsistent, then so is the intuitionistic equivalent. (Given that intuitionistic reasoning is classically valid, an inconsistency in the intuitionistic axioms trivially gives you one in the classical axioms.)

So the care that intuitionists take does not lead to any improvement in consistency.

However the two approaches lead to very different notions of what it means for something to mathematically exist. Despite the formal correspondences, they lead to very different concepts of mathematics.

I'm firmly of the belief that constructivism leads to concepts of existence that better fit the lay public than formalism does.

thadt 4 hours ago
Probably not. But this one time we had an argument and I made a statement along the lines of "I'm right, naturally." She went irrational. I lost the argument.

QED

btilly 4 hours ago
LOL

If she laughs at that kind of thing, I can see why you married her.

Etherlord87 5 hours ago
You don't need an implicit philosophical assumption, you just need to define what an infinity is and the comparison method.
nextaccountic 53 minutes ago
This looks like a philosophical stance in the philosophy of mathematics actually, and it's called formalism
btilly 4 hours ago
Here's a hint. When someone makes a reference to something that was actively debated for decades, and you're not familiar with said debates, you should probably assume that you're missing some piece of relevant knowledge.

https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/mathematics-constructive/ is one place that you could start filling in that gap.

edanm 5 hours ago
What leaps are "unprovable"? I'm curious, that doesn't sound right.

For sure there are valid arguments on whether or not to use certain axioms which allow or disallow some set theoretical constructions, but given ZFC, is there anything that follows that is unprovable?

btilly 4 hours ago
When you say "given ZFC", you're assuming a lot. Including a notion of mathematical existence which bears little relation to any concept that most lay people have of what mathematical existence might mean.

In particular, you have made sufficient assumptions to prove that almost all real numbers that exist can never be specified in any possible finite description. In what sense do they exist? You also wind up with weirder things. Such as well-specified finite problems that provably have a polynomial time algorithm to solve...but for which it is impossible to find or verify that algorithm, or put an upper bound on the constants in the algorithm. In what sense does that algorithm exist, and is finite?

Does that sound impossible? An example of an open problem whose algorithm may have those characteristics is an algorithm to decide which graphs can be drawn on a torus without any self-crossings.

If our notion of "exists" is "constructable", all possible mathematical things can fit inside of a countable universe. No set can have more than that.

edanm 3 hours ago
> When you say "given ZFC", you're assuming a lot.

Errr, I'm just assuming the axioms of ZFC. That's literally all I'm doing.

> In what sense do [numbers that can't be finitely specified] exist?

In the sense that we can describe rules that lead to them, and describe how to work with them.

I understand that you're trying to tie the notion of "existence" to constructability, and that's fine. That's one way to play the game. Another is to use ZFC and be fine with "weird, unintuitive to laypeople" outcomes. Both are interesting and valid things to do IMO. I'm just not sure why one is obviously "better" or "more real" or something. At the end, it's all just coming up with rules and figuring out what comes out of them.

btilly 1 hour ago
My point is that going from a lay understanding of mathematics to "just accept ZFC" means jumping past a variety of debatable philosophical points, and accepting a standard collection of answers to them. Mathematicians gloss over that.
somecontext 3 hours ago
> you're assuming a lot. Including a notion of mathematical existence which bears little relation to any concept that most lay people have of what mathematical existence might mean.

John Horton Conway:

> It's a funny thing that happens with mathematicians. What's the ontology of mathematical things? How do they exist? In what sense do they exist? There's no doubt that they do exist but you can't poke and prod them except by thinking about them. It's quite astonishing and I still don't understand it, having been a mathematician all my life. How can things be there without actually being there? There's no doubt that 2 is there or 3 or the square root of omega. They're very real things. I still don't know the sense in which mathematical objects exist, but they do. Of course, it's hard to say in what sense a cat is out there, too, but we know it is, very definitely. Cats have a stubborn reality but maybe numbers are stubborner still. You can't push a cat in a direction it doesn't want to go. You can't do it with a number either.

zozbot234 1 hour ago
> In what sense do they exist?

In the sense that all statements of non-constructive "existence" are made, viz. "you can't prove that they don't exist in the general case", so you are allowed to work under the stronger assumption that they also exist constructively, without any contradiction resulting. That can certainly be useful in some applications.

btilly 1 hour ago
Sure, we can choose to work in a set of axioms that says that there exists an oracle that can solve the Halting problem.

But the fact that such systems don't create contradictions emphatically *DOES NOT* demonstrate the constructive existence of such an oracle. Doubly not given that in various usual constructivist systems, it is easily provable that nothing that exists can serve as such an oracle.

drdeca 14 minutes ago
If such a system proved that the answer to some decidable question was x, when the actual answer was y, then the system would prove a contradiction. If the system doesn’t prove a contradiction, then that situation doesn’t happen, so you can trust its answers to decidable questions.

If the only questions you accept as meaningful are the decidable ones, then you can trust its answers for all the questions you accept as meaningful and for which it has answers.

Also, “provable that nothing that exists can serve as such an oracle” seems pretty presumptive about what things can exist? Shouldn’t that be more like, “nothing which can be given in such-and-such way (essentially, no computable procedure) can be such an oracle”?

Why treat it as axiomatic that nothing that isn’t Turing-computable can exist? It seems unlikely that any finite physical object can compute any deterministic non-Turing-computable function (because it seems like state spaces for bounded regions of space have bounded dimension), but that’s not something that should be a priori, I think.

I guess it wouldn’t really be verifiable if such a machine did exist, because we would have no way to confirm that it never errs? Ah, wait, no, maybe using the MIP* = RE result, maybe we could in principle use that to test it?

zozbot234 1 hour ago
> emphatically DOES NOT demonstrate the constructive existence of such an oracle

Of course, but it shows that you can assume that such an oracle exists whenever you are working under additional conditions where the existence of such a "special case" oracle makes sense to you, even though you can't show its existence in the general case. This outlook generalizes to all non-constructive existence statements (and disjunctive statements, as appropriate). It's emphatically not the same as constructive existence, but it can nonetheless be useful.

btilly 58 minutes ago
That's like asserting the existence of a bank account in my name with a billion dollars in it that I know nothing about.

I won't ever be able to find a contradiction from that claim, because I have no way to find that bank account if it exists.

But that argument also won't convince me that the bank account exists.

zozbot234 48 minutes ago
That argument ought to convince you that there's a mere "possible world" where that bank account turns out to exist. Sometimes we are implicitly interested in these special-cased "possible worlds", even though they'll involve conditions that we aren't quite sure about. Non-constructive existence is nothing more than a handy way of talking about such things, compared to the constructively correct "it's not the case that the existence of X is always falsified".
tempfile 3 hours ago
You are being very cryptic. Are you trying to say that the existence of uncountable sets requires the axiom of choice? If you are, that's false. If you aren't, I'm not sure what you are trying to say.
btilly 1 hour ago
I'm definitely not trying to say that the existence of uncountable sets requires the axiom of choice. Cantor's diagonalization argument for the reals demonstrates otherwise.

I'm saying that to go from the uncountability of the reals to the idea that this implies that the infinity of the reals is larger, requires making some important philosophical assumptions. Constructivism demonstrates that uncountable need not mean more.

On the algorithm example, you could have asked what I was referring to.

The result that I was referencing follows from the https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Robertson%E2%80%93Seymour_theo.... The theorem says that any class of finite graphs which is closed under graph minors, must be completely characterized by a finite set of forbidden minors. Given that set of forbidden minors, we can construct a polynomial time test for membership in the class - just test each forbidden minor in turn.

The problem is that the theorem is nonconstructive. While it classically proves that the set exists, it provides no way to find it. Worse yet, it can be proven that in general there is no way to find or verify the minimal solution. Or even to provide an upper bound on the number of forbidden minors that will be required.

This need not hold in special cases. For example planar graphs are characterized by 2 forbidden minors.

For the toroidal graphs, as https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Toroidal_graph will verify, the list of known forbidden minors currently has 17,523 graphs. We have no idea how many more there will be. Nor do we have any reason to believe that it is possible to verify the complete list in ZFC. Therefore the polynomial time algorithm that Robinson-Seymour says must exist, does not seem to exist in any meaningful and useful way. Such as, for example, being findable or provably correct from ZFC.

ogogmad 2 hours ago
He never mentioned the Axiom of Choice. I think he articulated his opinion clearly enough. It's his own subjective value judgement.
ogogmad 2 hours ago
It might be relevant to look at this: https://home.sandiego.edu/~shulman/papers/jmm2022-complement...

Also this: https://arxiv.org/pdf/1212.6543

Assuming you haven't looked at these already, of course.

btilly 57 minutes ago
I had already read the second. I'm not so enthused about the first.
N0isRESFe8GXmqR 2 hours ago
[dead]
Tazerenix 8 hours ago
>Today, mathematics is regarded as an abstract science.

Pure mathematics is regarded as an abstract science, which it is by definition. Arnol'd argued vehemently and much more convincingly for the viewpoint that all mathematics is (and must be) linked to the natural sciences.

>On forums such as Stack Exchange, trained mathematicians may sneer at newcomers who ask for intuitive explanations of mathematical constructs.

Mathematicians use intuition routinely at all levels of investigation. This is captured for example by Tao's famous stages of rigour (https://terrytao.wordpress.com/career-advice/theres-more-to-...). Mathematicians require that their intuition is useful for mathematics: if intuition disagrees with rigour, the intuition must be discarded or modified so that it becomes a sharper, more useful razor. If intuition leads one to believe and pursue false mathematical statements, then it isn't (mathematical) intuition after all. Most beginners in mathematics do not have the knowledge to discern the difference (because mathematics is very subtle) and many experts lack the patience required to help navigate beginners through building (and appreciating the importance of) that intuition.

The next paragraph about how mathematics was closely coupled to reality for most of history and only recently with our understanding of infinite sets became too abstract is not really at all accurate of the history of mathematics. Euclid's Elements is 2300 years old and is presented in a completely abstract way.

The mainstream view in mathematics is that infinite sets, especially ones as pedestrian as the naturals or the reals, are not particularly weird after all. Once one develops the aforementioned mathematical intuition (that is, once one discards the naive, human-centric notion that our intuition about finite things should be the "correct" lens through which to understand infinite things, and instead allows our rigorous understanding of infinite sets to inform our intuition for what to expect) the confusion fades away like a mirage. That process occurs for all abstract parts of mathematics as one comes to appreciate them (expect, possibly, for things like spectral sequences).

gaze 1 hour ago
The only things that are weird in math are things that would not be expected after understanding the definitions. A lot of the early hurdles in mathematics are just learning and gaining comfort with the fact that the object under scrutiny is nothing more than what it's defined to be.
pdpi 7 hours ago
> Pure mathematics is regarded as an abstract science, which it is by definition.

I'd argue that, by definition, mathemtatics is not, and cannot be, a science. Mathematics deals with provable truths, science cannot prove truth and must deal falsifiability instead.

abdullahkhalids 5 hours ago
Mathematical proofs are checked by noisy finite computational machines (humans). Even computer proofs' inputs-outputs are interpreted by humans. Your uncertainty in a theorem is lower bounded by the inherent error rate of human brains.
drdeca 3 minutes ago
This may be, but not, I think, in a way that is particularly worth modeling?

When we try to model something probabilistically, it is usually not a great idea to model the probability that we made an error in our probability calculations as part of our calculations of the probability.

Ultimately, we must act. It does no good to suppose that “perhaps all of our beliefs are incoherent and we are utterly incapable of reason”.

goatlover 1 hour ago
Plenty of mathematical proofs have been proven true with 100% certainty. Complicated proofs that involve a lot of steps and checking can have errors. They can also be proven true if exhaustively checked.
naasking 32 minutes ago
> Plenty of mathematical proofs have been proven true with 100% certainty

Solipsists would like to have a word with you...

myrmidon 7 hours ago
You could turn the argument around and say that math must be a science because it builds on falsifiable hypotheses and makes testable predictions.

In the end arguing about whether mathematics is a science or not makes no more sense than bickering about tomates being fruit; can be answered both yes and no using reasonable definitions.

pdpi 7 hours ago
> In the end arguing about whether mathematics is a science or not makes no more sense than bickering about tomates being fruit

That's the thing, though — It does make sense, and it's an important distinction. There is a reason why "mathematical certainty" is an idiom — we collectively understand that maths is in the business of irrefutable truths. I find that a large part of science skepticism comes from the fundamental misunderstanding that science is, like maths, in the business of irrefutable truths, when it is actually in the business of temporarily holding things as true until they're proven false. Because of this misunderstanding, skeptics assume that science being proven wrong is a deathblow to science itself instead of being an integral part of the process.

TimPC 7 hours ago
In general you aren't testing as an empiricist though, you are looking for a rational argument to prove or disprove something.
Tazerenix 7 hours ago
The practical experience of doing mathematics is actually quite close to a natural science, even if the subject is technically a "formal science* according to the conventional meanings of the terms.

Mathematicians actually do the same thing as scientists: hypothesis building by extensive investigation of examples. Looking for examples which catch the boundary of established knowledge and try to break existing assumptions, etc. The difference comes after that in the nature of the concluding argument. A scientist performs experiments to validate or refute the hypothesis, establishing scientific proof (a kind of conditional or statistical truth required only to hold up to certain conditions, those upon which the claim was tested). A mathematician finds and writes a proof or creates a counter example.

The failure of logical positivism and the rise of Popperian philosophy is obviously correct that we can't approach that end process in the natural sciences the way we do for maths, but the practical distinction between the subjects is not so clear.

This is all without mention the much tighter coupling between the two modes of investigation at the boundary between maths and science in subjects like theoretical physics. There the line blurs almost completely and a major tool used by genuine physicists is literally purusiing mathematical consistency in their theories. This has been used to tremendous success (GR, Yang-Mills, the weak force) and with some difficulties (string theory).

————

Einstein understood all this:

> If, then, it is true that the axiomatic basis of theoretical physics cannot be extracted from experience but must be freely invented, can we ever hope to find the right way? Nay, more, has this right way any existence outside our illusions? Can we hope to be guided safely by experience at all when there exist theories (such as classical mechanics) which to a large extent do justice to experience, without getting to the root of the matter? I answer without hesitation that there is, in my opinion, a right way, and that we are capable of finding it. Our experience hitherto justifies us in believing that nature is the realisation of the simplest conceivable mathematical ideas. I am convinced that we can discover by means of purely mathematical constructions the concepts and the laws connecting them with each other, which furnish the key to the understanding of natural phenomena. Experience may suggest the appropriate mathematical concepts, but they most certainly cannot be deduced from it. Experience remains, of course, the sole criterion of the physical utility of a mathematical construction. But the creative principle resides in mathematics. In a certain sense, therefore, I hold it true that pure thought can grasp reality, as the ancients dreamed. - Albert Einstein

2snakes 4 hours ago
An alternative to abstraction is to use iconic forms and boundary math (containerization and void-based reasoning). See Laws of Form and William Bricken's books recently. Using a unary operator instead of binary (Boolean) does indeed seem simpler, in keeping with Nature. Introduction: https://www.frontiersin.org/journals/psychology/articles/10....
nitwit005 2 hours ago
A proof is just an argument that something is true. Ideally, you've made an extremely strong argument, but it's still a human making a claim something is true. Plenty of published proofs have been shown to be false.

Math is scientific in the sense that you've proposed a hypothesis, and others can test it.

goatlover 1 hour ago
Difference is mathematical arguments can be shown to be provably true when exhaustively checked (which is straight forward with simpler proofs). Something you don't get with the empirical sciences.

Also the empirical part means natural phenomena needs to be involved. Math can be purely abstract.

nitwit005 47 minutes ago
You're making a strong argument if you believe you checked every possibility, but it's still just an argument.

If you want to escape human fallibility, I'm afraid you're going to need divine intervention. Works checked as carefully as possible still seem to frequently feature corrections.

Aardwolf 3 hours ago
I'm not sure if it deals only with provable truths? It even deals with the concept of unprovability itself, if the incompleteness theorem is considered part of mathematics
ubj 6 hours ago
Science involves both deductive and inductive reasoning. I would in turn argue that mathematics is a science that focuses heavily (but not entirely) on deductive reasoning.
The_suffocated 7 hours ago
Somewhat tangential to the discussion: I have once read that Richard Feynman was opposed to the idea (originally due to Karl Popper) that falsifiability is central to physics, but I haven't read any explanation.
GLdRH 7 hours ago
He probably means science in a wider sense as opposed to the anglo-american narrower sense where science is just physics, chemistry, biology and similar topics.
weinzierl 7 hours ago
Pure mathematics is just symbol pushing and can never be science. It is lot of fun though and as it turned out occasionally pretty useful for science.
lo_zamoyski 6 hours ago
It is absolutely a science, a formal science. What it isn't is an empirical science.

The "symbol pushing" is a methodological tool, and a very useful one that opened up the possibility of new expansive fields of mathematics.

(Of course, it is important to always distinguish between properties of the abstraction or the tool from the object of study.)

weinzierl 6 hours ago
Well, we are talking about pure mathematics and there is not much Popperian scientific method in it.
Warwolt 4 hours ago
Who cares? That's just semantics. If we define science as the systematic search for truths, then mathematics and logic are the paradigmic sciences. If we define it as only empirical search for truth then perhaps that excludes mathematics, but it's an entirely unintersting point, since it says nothing.
AlexandrB 7 hours ago
Mathematical "truth" all depends on what axioms you start with. So, in a sense, it doesn't prove "truth" either - just systemic consistency[1] given those starting axioms. Science at least grapples with observable phenomena in the universe.

[1] And even this has limits: https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Gödel%27s_incompleteness_theor...

tiahura 7 hours ago
Mathematics is a science of formal systems. Proofs are its experiments, axioms its assumptions. Both math and science test consistency—one internally, the other against nature. Different methods, same spirit of systematic inquiry.
lo_zamoyski 6 hours ago
It's not an empirical science, but it is a science, where "science" means any systematic body of knowledge of an aspect of a thing and its causes under a certain method. (In that sense, most of what are considered scientific fields are families of sciences.) Mathematics is what you'd call a formal science with formal structure and quantity as its object of study and deductive inference and analysis as its primary methods (the cause of greatest interest is the formal cause).
ndriscoll 7 hours ago
Not only is intuition important (or the entire point; anyone with some basic training or even a computer can follow rules to do formal symbol manipulation. It's the intuition for what symbol manipulation to do when that's interesting), but it is literally discussed in a helpful, nonjudgmental way on Math Stack Exchange. e.g.

https://math.stackexchange.com/questions/31859/what-concept-...

Other great sources for quick intuition checks are Wikipedia and now LLMs, but mainly through putting in the work to discover the nuances that exist or learning related topics to develop that wider context for yourself.

nkrisc 6 hours ago
> The next paragraph about how mathematics was closely coupled to reality for most of history and only recently with our understanding of infinite sets became too abstract is not really at all accurate of the history of mathematics. Euclid's Elements is 2300 years old and is presented in a completely abstract way.

I may be off-base as an outsider to mathematics, but Euclid’s Elements, per my understanding, is very much grounded in the physical reality of the shapes and relationships he describes, if you were to physically construct them.

empath75 6 hours ago
Quite the opposite, Plato, several hundred years before Euclid was already talking about geometry as abstract, and indeed the world of ideas and mathematics as being _more real_ than the physical world, and Euclid is very much in that tradition.

I am going to quote from the _very beginning_ of the elements:

Definition 1. A point is that which has no part. Definition 2. A line is breadthless length.

Both of these two definitions are impossible to construct physically right off the bat.

All of the physically realized constructions of shapes were considered to basically be shadows of an idealized form of them.

kannanvijayan 6 hours ago
Another point to keep in mind is that a lot of mathematics that's not considered abstract _now_ was definitely considered "hopelessly" abstract at the time of its conception.

The complex number system started being explored by the greeks long before any notion of the value of complex spaces existed, and could be mapped to something in reality.

mrguyorama 27 minutes ago
Hell, 0 used to be considered too abstract!
rob74 7 hours ago
How has mathematics gotten so abstract? My understanding was that mathematics was abstract from the very beginning. Sure, you can say that two cows plus two more cows makes four cows, but that already is an abstraction - someone who has no knowledge of math might object that one cow is rarely exactly the same as another cow, so just assigning the value "1" to any cow you see is an oversimplification. Of course, simple examples such as this can be translated into intuitive concepts more easily, but they are still abstract.
stonemetal12 6 hours ago
Mathematics arose from ancient humans need to count and measure. Even the invention\discovery of Calculus was in service to physics. It has probably only been 300 years or so since Mathematics has been symbolic, before that it was more geometric and more attached to the physical world.

Leibniz (late 1600s) helped to popularize negative numbers. At the time most mathematicians thought they were "absurd" and "fictitious".

No, not highly abstract from the beginning.

anthk 10 minutes ago
compressedgas 5 hours ago
> Leibniz (late 1600s) helped to popularize negative numbers.

Wasn't that imaginary numbers?

empath75 6 hours ago
Almost from the first time people started writing about mathematics, they were writing about it in an abstract way. The Egyptians and the Babylonians kept things relatively concrete and mostly stuck to word problems (although lists of pythagorean triples is evidence for very early "number theory"), but Greece, China and India were all working in abstractions relatively early.
hollerith 6 hours ago
In particular, ancient Greek geometry at least after 300 BC proceeded from axioms, which is a central component of the abstract approach.
elliotec 6 hours ago
Sorry what? Ancient humans invented symbols to count. How is that not symbolic?

Geometry is “attached” to the physical world… but in an abstract way… but you can point to the thing your measuring maybe so it doesn’t count…

Abstraction was perfected if not invented by mathematics.

Ekaros 2 hours ago
Symbolic here refers of doing math with place holders, be it letters or something. Ancient world had notations for recording numbers. But much less so to do math with them. Say like long division.
elliotec 6 hours ago
Right? Math is abstraction at its very core. Ridiculous premise acting as if this is anything but beyond ancient.
TuringTest 7 hours ago
> My understanding was that mathematics was abstract from the very beginning.

It wasn't; but that's a common misunderstanding from hundreds of centuries of common practice.

So, how has maths gotten so abstract? Easy, it has been taken over by abstraction astronauts(1), which have existed throghout all eras (and not just for software engineering).

Mathematics was created by unofficial engineers as a way to better accomplish useful activities (guessing the best time of year to start migrating, and later harvesting; counting what portion of harvest should be collected to fill the granaries for the whole winter; building temples for the Pharaoh that wouldn't collapse...)

But then, it was adopted by thinkers that enjoyed the activity by itself and started exploring it by sheer joy; math stopped representing "something that needed doing in an efficient way", and was considered "something to think about to the last consecuences".

Then it was merged into philosophy, with considerations about perfect regular solids, or things like the (misunderstood) metaphor of shadows in Plato's cave (which people interpreted as being about duality of the essences, when it was merely an allegory on clarity of thinking and explanation). Going from an intuitive physical reality such as natural numbers ("we have two cows", or "two fingers") to the current understanding of numbers as an abstract entity ("the universe has the essence of number 'two' floating beyond the orbit of Uranus"(2)) was a consequence of that historical process, when layers upon layers of abstraction took thinkers further and further away from the practical origins of math.

[1] https://www.joelonsoftware.com/2001/04/21/dont-let-architect...

[2] https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Hyperuranion

taeric 6 hours ago
I think it is fair to say that it was always an abstraction. But, crucially, it was built on language as much as it was empiricism.

That is, numbers were specifically used to abstract over how other things behave using simple and strict rules. No?

TuringTest 5 hours ago
> That is, numbers were specifically used to abstract over how other things behave using simple and strict rules. No?

Agree that math is built on language. But math is not any specific set of abstractions; time and again mathematicians have found out that if you change the definitions and axioms, you achieve a quite different set of abstractions (different numbers, geometries, infinity sets...). Does it mean that the previous math ceases to exist when you find a contradiction on it? No, it's just that you start talking about new objects, because you have gained new knowledge.

The math is not in the specific objects you find, it's in the process to find them. Rationalism consider on thinking one step at a time with rigor. Math is the language by which you explain rational thought in a very precise, unambiguous way. You can express many different thoughts, even inconsistent ones, with the same precise language of mathematics.

taeric 5 hours ago
Agreed that we grew math to be that way. But there is an easy to trace history on the names of the numbers. Reals, Rationals, Imaginary, etc. They were largely named based on their relation to the language on how to relate them to physical things.
lo_zamoyski 6 hours ago
It is abstract in the strict sense, of course. Every science is, as "abstract" simply means "not concrete". All reasoning is by definition abstract in the sense it all reasoning by definition involved concepts, and concepts are by definition abstract.

Numbers, for example, are abstract in the sense that you cannot find concrete numbers walking around or falling off trees or whatever. They're quantities abstracted from concrete particulars.

What the author is concerned with is how mathematics became so abstract.

You have abstractions that bear no apparent relation to concrete reality, at least not according to any direct correspondence. You have degrees of abstraction that generalize various fields of mathematics in a way that are increasingly far removed from concrete reality.

btilly 5 hours ago
Proposed rule: People writing about the history of mathematics, should learn something about the history of mathematics.

Mathematicians didn't just randomly decide to go to abstraction and the foundations of mathematics. They were forced there by a series of crises where the mathematics that they knew fell apart. For example Joseph Fourier came up with a way to add up a bunch of well-behaved functions - sin and cos - and came up to something that wasn't considered a function - a square wave.

The focus on abstraction and axiomatization came after decades of trying to repair mathematics over and over again. Trying to retell the story in terms of the resulting mathematical flow of the ideas, completely mangles the actual flow of events.

coffeeaddict1 1 hour ago
I have to disagree with this. Modern (pure) mathematics is abstract and very often completely detached from practical applications because of culture and artistic inspiration. There is no "objectivity" driving modern pure mathematics. It exists mostly because people like thinking about it. Any connection to the real world is often a coincidence or someone outside the field noticing that something (really just a tiny-tiny amount) in pure maths could be useful.

> forced there by a series of crises where the mathematics that they knew fell apart

This can be said to be true of those working in foundations, but the vast majority of mathematicians are completely uninterested in that! In fact, most mathematicians today probably can't cite you the set-theoretic (or any other foundation) axioms that they use every day, if you ask them point-blank.

crabbone 5 hours ago
Yeah... The article doesn't even attempt to answer the question in its title. It's just a watered down Intro to Mathematics 101.
susam 2 hours ago
This article explores a particular kind of abstractness in mathematics, especially the construction of numbers and the cardinalities of infinite sets. It is all very interesting indeed.

However, the kind of abstractness I most enjoy in mathematics is found in algebraic structures such as groups and rings, or even simpler structures like magmas and monoids. These structures avoid relying on specific types of numbers or elements, and instead focus on the relationships and operations themselves. For me, this reveals an even deeper beauty, i.e., different domains of mathematics, or even problems in computer science, can be unified under the same algebraic framework.

Consider, for example, the fact that the set of real numbers forms a vector space over the set of rationals. Can it get more abstract than that? We know such a vector space must have a basis, but what would that basis even look like? The existence of such a basis (Hamel basis) is guaranteed by the axioms and proofs, yet it defies explicit description. That, to me, is the most intriguing kind of abstractness!

Despite being so abstract, the same algebraic structures find concrete applications in computing, for example, in the form of coding theory. Concepts such as polynomial rings and cosets of subspaces over finite fields play an important role in error-correcting codes, without which modern data transmission and storage would not exist in their current form.

Animats 1 hour ago
Infinity is a convenience that pays off in terseness. There's constructive mathematics, but it's wordy and has lots of cases. You can escape undecidablity if you give up infinity. Most mathematicians consider that a bad trade.
johngossman 6 hours ago
I think the title is a little tongue in cheek. The rest of the blog post develops the Foundations of arithmetic in a clear, well-grounded manner. This is probably a really good introduction for someone about to take a Foundations course. I say this having just Potter's "Set Theory and it's Philosophy" which covers the same material (and a lot more obviously) in 300 some pages. Another good introduction is Frederic Schuller's YouTube lectures, though already there you can start to see the over abstraction.
tphyahoo2 2 hours ago
Just drop the axiom of infinity and quit whining.

https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Ultrafinitism

boxerab 6 hours ago
The French Bourbaki school certainly had a large influence on increasing abstraction in math, with their rallying cry "Down With Triangles". The more fundamental reason is that generalizing a problem works; it distills the essence and allows machinery from other branches of math to help solve it.

"A mathematician is a person who can find analogies between theorems; a better mathematician is one who can see analogies between proofs and the best mathematician can notice analogies between theories. One can imagine that the ultimate mathematician is one who can see analogies between analogies."

-- Stefan Banach

initramfs 1 hour ago
This article can also be written as "The unreasonable effectiveness of abstraction in mathematics."
BrandoElFollito 1 hour ago
I used to be a physicist and I love math for the toolbox it provides (mostly Analysis). It allows to solve a physical model and make predictions.

When I was studying, I always got top marks in Analysis.

Then came Algebra, Topology and similar nightmares. Oh crap, that was difficult. Not really because of the complexity, but rather because of abstraction, an abstraction I could not take to physics (I was not a very good physicist either). This is the moment I realized that I will never be "good in maths" and that will remain a toolbox to me.

Fast forward 30 years, my son has differentials in high school (France, math was one of his "majors").

He comes to me to ask what the fuck it is (we have a unhealthy fascination for maths in France, and teach them the same was as in 1950). It is only when we went from physical models to differentials that it became clear. We did again the trip Newton did - physics rocks :)

doe88 8 hours ago
My mental representation of this phenomenon is like inverted Russian dolls: you start by learning the inner layers, the basics, and as you mature, you work your way into more abstractions, more unified theories, more structures, adding layers as you learn more and more. Adding difficulty but this extreme refinement is also very beautiful. When studying mathematics I like to think of all these steps, all the people, and centuries of trial and errors, refinements it took to arrive where we are now.
trinsic2 1 hour ago
>Next, consider the time needed for Achilles to reach the yellow dot; once again, by the time he gets there, the turtle will have moved forward a tiny bit. This process can be continued indefinitely; the gap keeps getting smaller but never goes to zero, so we must conclude that Achilles can’t possibly win the race.

Am i daft, eventually (Very soon) Achilles would over take the turtles position regardless of how far it moved... I am missing something?

m_dupont 1 hour ago
you're not, the proof is a famous error known as zenos paradox. Its only an apparent paradox, and indeed it's been disproven by observing that things do in fact move
trinsic2 1 hour ago
Wow this is some serious over complication. How can anyone mix Philosophy and Mathematics? They are not even in the same ball park.. Even with infinity. Its just something that cant be understood in the mind, IMHO.
The_suffocated 6 hours ago
Discussions of this sort can easily get chaotic, because people tend to conflate intuitiveness and concreteness. Sometimes the whole point of abstraction is to make a concept clearer and more intuitive. The distinction between polynomial function and polynomial is an example.
intrasight 7 hours ago
There was a time, not that long ago in human history, that zero was "so abstract".
stonemetal12 6 hours ago
Sure even 500 years ago negative numbers were "absurd" in western mathematics and even in eastern mathematics where they were used they were more thought of as credits and debts than just abstract numbers.
dist-epoch 7 hours ago
It was a religious offense to talk about zero.

https://cambriamathtutors.com/zero-christianity/

pgustafs 6 hours ago
The definition of bijection is much more interesting than comparing cardinals. Many everyday use cases where (structure-preserving) bijections make it clear that two apriori different objects can be treated similarly.

More generally, mathematics is experimental not just in the sense that it can be used to make physical predictions, but also (probably more importantly) in that definitions are "experiments" whose outcome is judged by their usefulness.

falcor84 7 hours ago
I found it a bit ironic that the author introduced C code there as an aid, but didn't incorporate it into their argument. As I see it, code is exactly the bridge between abstract math and the empirical world - the process of writing code to implement your mathematical structure and then seeing if it gives you the output you expect (or better yet, with Lean, if it proves your proposition) essentially makes math a natural science again.
Ar-Curunir 2 hours ago
No, the correctness of your implementation is a mathematical statement about a computation running a particular computational environment, and can be reasoned about from first principles without ever invoking a computer. Whether your computation gives reasonable outputs on certain inputs says nothing (in general) about the original mathematics.
falcor84 9 minutes ago
> Whether your computation gives reasonable outputs on certain inputs says nothing (in general) about the original mathematics.

While mathematics "can" be reasoned about from first principles, the history of math is chock-full of examples of professional mathematicians convinced by unsound and wrong arguments. I prefer the clarity of testing the math on a computer.

7 hours ago
jmount 5 hours ago
None of that was even the abstract stuff. It is all models of sizes, order, and inclusion (integers, cardinals, ordinals, sets). Not the nastier abstractions of partial orders, associativity, composition and so on (lattices, categories, ...).
lambdasquirrel 5 hours ago
And yet it all circles back.

We used Peano arithmetic when doing C++ template metaprogramming anytime a for loop from 0..n was needed. It was fun and games as long as you didn't make a mistake because the compiler errors would be gnarly. The Haskell people still do stuff like this, and I wouldn't be surprised if someone were doing it in Scala's type system as well.

Also, the PLT people are using lattices and categories to formalize their work.

aristofun 7 hours ago
How has blog posts authors gotten so uneducated or/and clickbaiting?

Math in its core has always been abstract. It’s the whole point.

The_suffocated 5 hours ago
> Math in its core has always been abstract. It’s the whole point.

I don't think so. E.g. there may be some abstractions in numerical linear algebra, but the subject matter has always been quite concrete.

elAhmo 7 hours ago
Isn't this true for many other fields of study?

Given the collective time put into it, easier stuff was already solved thousands of years ago, and people are not really left with something trivial to work on. Hence focusing on more and more abstract things as those are the only things left to do something novel.

currymj 6 hours ago
two interesting cases: convex analysis and linear algebra are both relatively easy, concrete areas of mathematics. also beautiful and unbelievably useful. yet they didn't develop until the 19th century and didn't mature until the 20th.
dist-epoch 7 hours ago
You are right, the low hanging fruits were picked a long time ago.

But also wrong, the easier stuff was solved INCORRECTLY thousands of years ago. But it takes advanced math to understand what was incorrect about it.

iamwil 7 hours ago
It's always been abstract. They'll say to me, "Give me a concrete example with numbers!"

I get what they're saying in practice. But numbers are abstract. They only seem concrete because you'd internalized the abstract concept.

daxfohl 6 hours ago
One could also say the opposite. It's not abstract at all, just a set of rules and their implications. Plausibly the least abstract thing there is.

On the other hand, two cookies plus three cookies, what even is a cookie? What if they're different sizes? Do sandwich cookies count as one or two? If you cut one in half, does you count it as two cookies now? All very abstract. Just give me some concrete definitions and rules and I'll give you a concrete answer.

nivter 6 hours ago
I believe that abstraction is recursive in nature which creates multiple layers of abstract ideas leading to new areas or insights. For instance our understanding of continuity and limit led to calculus, which when tied to the (abstract) idea of linearity led to the idea of linear operator which explains various phenomena in the real world surprisingly well.
masklinn 6 hours ago
You could say that abstraction is a step or a ladder: by climbing on an abstraction you can see new goals and opportunities, possibly out of reach until you build yet new steps.
lottin 1 hour ago
I wish the scroll bar was a little less invisible.
hodgehog11 8 hours ago
I feel like a great deal more credit should be given to Cauchy and his school, but I understand the tale is long enough.

The Peano axioms are pretty nifty though. To get a better appreciation of the difficulty of formally constructing the integers as we know them, I recommend trying the Numbers Game in Lean found here: https://adam.math.hhu.de/

yuppiemephisto 5 hours ago
I like Peano, but he was using Grassmann's definition of natural numbers
jjgreen 7 hours ago
The number 1 is what a cow, a fox, a stone ... have in common, oneness. Mathematics is abstraction, written down.
prmph 1 hour ago
That's not obvious.

- they are material objects

- they are concepts I understand

- they are sequences of letters

- they are English words

- ...

Not sure why oneness is privileged as what they have in common, and their oneness is meaningless by itself. Oneness is a property that is only meaningful in relation to other concepts of objects.

jjgreen 32 minutes ago
A rock is not physically a material object, it is a region of space where the electrons, protons and neutrons are differently arranged, and that region is fuzzy, difficult to determine; but as physical beings, as monkeys, we recognise its oneness, that's necessary for our survival in this physical world, we see this blurred outline of a rock, we feel it's weight in our hand, we observe its practical difference from two rocks. Just as we recognise twoness in a pair of rocks, fish, apples, threeness in a triple of parrots, of carrots, we abstract those out into 1, 2, 3, ...
fidotron 7 hours ago
Unlike Zeno's famous example the paradox which does better at explaining the problem is https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Coastline_paradox which Mandelbrot seemed particularly keen on.

The tendency towards excessive abstraction is the same as the use of jargon in other fields: it just serves to gatekeep everything. The history of mathematics (and science) is actually full of amateurs, priests and bored aristocrats that happened to help make progress, often in their spare time.

OkayPhysicist 5 hours ago
Complaining about jargon is lazy. Most communications about complicated things are not aimed at the layman, because to do anything useful with the complicated things, you tend to have to understand a fair amount of the context of the field. Once you're committed to actually learning about the field, the jargon is the easiest part: they're just words or phrases that mean something very specific.

To put it another way: Jargon is the source code of the sciences. To an outsider, looking in on software development, they see the somewhat impenetrable wall of parentheses and semicolons and go "Ah, that's why programming is hard: you have to understand code". And I hope everyone here can understand that that's an uninformed thing to say. Syntax is the easy part of programming, it was made specifically to make expressing the rigorous problem solving easier. Jargon is the same way: it exists to make expressing very specific things that only people in this subfield actually think about easier, instead of having to vaguely gesture at the concept, or completely redefine it every time anybody wants to communicate within the field.

ndriscoll 5 hours ago
Abstraction isn't to gatekeep; it's to increase the utility. It's the same as "dependency inversion" in programming: do your logic in terms of interfaces/properties, not in terms of a particular instance. This makes reasoning reusable. It also often makes things clearer by cutting out distracting details that aren't related to the core idea.

People are aware that you need context to motivate abstractions. That's why we start with numbers and fractions and not ideals and localizations.

Jargon in any field is to communicate quickly with precision. Again the point is not to gatekeep. It's that e.g. doctors spend a lot of time talking to other doctors about complex medical topics, and need a high bandwidth way to discuss things that may require a lot of nuance. The gatekeeping is not about knowing the words; it's knowing all of the information that the words are condensing.

azan_ 7 hours ago
Theirs no such thing as excessive abstraction in math, because abstraction is the point. Is category theory “excessive abstraction” in your opinion?
fidotron 7 hours ago
> because abstraction is the point.

Formal reasoning is the point, which is not by itself abstraction.

Someone else in this discussion is saying Euclid's Elements is abstract, which is near complete nonsense. If that is abstract our perception of everything except for the fundamental [whatever] we are formed of is an abstraction.

empath75 6 hours ago
> Formal reasoning is the point, which is not by itself abstraction.

What do you think "formal" means in that sentence.

It means "formal" from the word "form". It is reasoning through pure manipulation of symbols, with no relation to the external world required.

fidotron 6 hours ago
I love how you lot just redefine words to suit your purpose:

https://www.etymonline.com/word/formal "late 14c., "pertaining to form or arrangement;" also, in philosophy and theology, "pertaining to the form or essence of a thing," from Old French formal, formel "formal, constituent" (13c.) and directly from Latin formalis, from forma "a form, figure, shape" (see form (n.)). From early 15c. as "in due or proper form, according to recognized form," As a noun, c. 1600 (plural) "things that are formal;" as a short way to say formal dance, recorded by 1906 among U.S. college students."

There's not a much better description of what Euclid was doing.

empath75 6 hours ago
I am not, this is what formal logic and formal reasoning means:

https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/logic-classical/

"Formal" in logic has a very precise technical meaning.

fidotron 5 hours ago
What you mean is someone has redefined the word to suit their purpose, which is precisely what I pointed out at the top.

Edit to add: this comment had a sibling, that was suggesting that given a specific proof assistant requires all input to be formal logic perhaps the word formal could be redefined to mean that which is accepted by the proof assistant. Sadly this fine example of my point has been deleted.

hollerith 2 hours ago
Every mathematician understands what a formal proof is. Ditto a formal statement of a mathematical or logical proposition. The mathematicians of 100 years ago also all understood, and the meaning hasn't changed over the 100 years.
fidotron 2 hours ago
> The mathematicians of 100 years ago also all understood, and the meaning hasn't changed over the 100 years.

Isn't that the subject of the whole argument? That mathematicians have taken the road off in a very specific direction, and everyone disagreeing is ejected from the field, rather like occurred more recently in theoretical physics with string theory.

Prior to that time quite clearly you had formal proofs which do not meet the symbolic abstraction requirements that pure mathematicians apparently believe are axiomatic to their field today, even if they attempt to pretend otherwise, as argued over the case of Euclid elsewhere. If the Pythagoreans were reincarnated, as they probably expected, they would no doubt be dismissed as crackpots by these same people.

6 hours ago
azan_ 4 hours ago
No, abstraction is the point and formal reasoning is a tool. And yes, what Euclid did is obviously abstraction, I don’t know why so you consider this stance nonsense.
fidotron 3 hours ago
Can you say how mathematics is inherently abstract in a way consistent with your day-to-day life as a concrete person? Or is your personhood also an abstraction?

I could construct a formal reasoning scheme involving rules and jugs on my table, where we can pour liquids from one to another. It would be in no way symbolic, since it could use the liquids directly to simply be what they are. Is constructing and studing such a mechanism not mathematics? Similarly with something like musical intervals.

azan_ 3 hours ago
Of course I can. I frequently use numbers which are great abstraction. I can use same number five to describe apples, bananas and everything countable.
fidotron 3 hours ago
> to describe apples, bananas and everything countable

An apple is an abstraction over the particles/waves that comprise it, as is a banana.

Euclid is no more abstract than the day to day existence of a normal person, hence to claim that it is unusually abstract is to ignore, as you did, the abstraction inherent in day to day life.

As I pointed out it's very possible to create formal reasoning systems which are not symbolic or abstract, but due to that are we to assume constructing or studying them would not be a mathematical exercise? In fact the Pythagoreans did all sorts of stuff like that.

azan_ 2 hours ago
> An apple is an abstraction over the particles/waves that comprise it, as is a banana.

No, you don’t understand what abstraction is. Apple is exactly arrangement of particles, it’s not abstraction over them.

> hence to claim that it is unusually abstract

Who talks about him being unusually abstract (and not just abstract)?

> is to ignore, as you did, the abstraction inherent in day to day life.

How am I ignoring this abstraction when I’ve provided you exactly that (numbers are abstraction inherent in day to day life). I’m sorry but you seem to be discussing in bad faith.

fidotron 2 hours ago
> Apple is exactly arrangement of particles, it’s not abstraction over them.

No. You can do things to that apple, such as bite it, and it is still an apple, despite it now having a different set of particles. It is the abstract concept of appleness (which we define . . . somehow) applied to that arrangement of particles.

> I’m sorry but you seem to be discussing in bad faith.

Really?

> No, you don’t understand what abstraction is.

ogogmad 2 hours ago
"Indeed, persistently trying to relate the foundations of math to reality has become the calling card of online cranks." <-- Hm??? I'm getting self-conscious. Details?
s20n 6 hours ago
I believe mathematics was much tamer before Georg Cantor's work. If I had to pick a specific point in history when maths got "so abstract", it would be the introduction of axiomatic set theory by Zermelo.

I personally cannot wrap my head around Cantor's infinitary ideas, but I'm sure it makes perfect sense to people with better mathematical intuition than me.

bmitc 8 hours ago
What else is it supposed to do?
TZubiri 8 hours ago
[flagged]
fridek 7 hours ago
I'm curious how you managed to find nothing on lcamtuf. He's one of the most famous Polish hackers from the 90s, then one the best security researchers Google had. Even if you live under a rock, the substack has an "about" section. If it wasn't for Michał I'd probably be a farmer today.
roel_v 8 hours ago
Did you bother to google his handle? While I don't know his pure mathematics credentials, he's nerd-famous enough to not warrant an introduction. In fact, you not recognizing it says something about you.
jlongr 7 hours ago
>he's nerd-famous enough to not warrant an introduction

What is nerd-famous supposed to be. He's at the center of some subjective in-group that exists in your head?

TZubiri 7 hours ago
To be fair, we are on hacker news. I did once use on of his programs, American Fuzzy Lopper (fake advertisement lawsuit incoming if its not american). So he is not nobody apparently
wizzwizz4 7 hours ago
He wrote the American Fuzzy Lop fuzzer, which was extremely influential – pretty much put fuzzing on the map.
ak1ng 8 hours ago
jumpingscript 8 hours ago